Depleted
Uranium And
International Law
By Nikhil Shah
23 October, 2004
Countercurrents.org
I. Introduction
The legality of
Depleted Uranium (DU) has become a contentious issue in the past decade
as the different health and environmental effects of its use have been
revealed.[1] Depleted Uranium is by definition a lethal radioactive
and toxic weapon, although the extent of its toxicity is disputed.[2]
While there are grounds to claim that the use of DU weapons violates
international law, a stronger case could be made for it violating the
principles of international environmental law as opposed to international
humanitarian law.[3] This is due to the lack of conclusive scientific
evidence about the effects of DU and the somewhat restrictive interpretation
of international humanitarian laws put for by the International Court
of Justice (ICJ) in the nuclear weapons case.[4] It would be easier
to show that the use of DU violates emerging principles of international
environmental law such as the precautionary principle and the principle
of intergenerational equity due the lower scientific threshold and greater
burden of proof on the party using a lethal substance like DU.[5]
Section II of this
article will give some background as to the controversy surrounding
the use of DU. Section III of this paper will talk about the humanitarian
laws of war as defined by the Hague and Geneva conventions and discuss
the dubious legality of DU under this criteria. Section IV will discuss
two different principles of international environmental law and how
DU use could be seen as a violation of them. Section V will conclude
by recapping the dangers of DU use and the need to use the existing
legal mechanisms in international law to limit its use and to eventually
lead to its prohibition.
II. The Politics
of Depleted Uranium
Depleted Uranium
is a waste product resulting from the enrichment process of natural
uranium and is used for both military and civil purposes.[6] As a metal
it is extremely thick and dense and when fired at a speed of 1,200 meters
per second it can pierce tank armor or a block of concrete three meters
underground.[7] This is because DU burns fiercely and rapidly and carbonizes
everything in its way while it is transformed into fine uranium oxide
powder.[8] The costs of using it are very minimal as it is a waste product
from the nuclear industry and it provides a partial solution of what
to do with nuclear waste.[9]
By definition depleted
uranium is extremely toxic.[10] Most renowned books on chemistry describe
it as toxic both from a chemical and radiological standpoint and state
that even a small dosage of exposure to the air can be lethal.[11] When
depleted uranium ammunitions hit their targets, they release radioactive
particles and dust containing toxic heavy-metal elements.[12] The uranium
is liable to spontaneous combustion and produces vapors that burn at
very high temperatures.[13] Depleted Uranium weapons were used by the
U.S. and U.K. in Iraq and Afghanistan and by NATO countries in Yugoslavia.[14]
The lethal radioactivity
of uranium poses risks to both the environment and human beings. DU
poses an external radiation hazard if the metal comes in contact with
or is close to a human body for a long period of time but it is the
most dangerous when it enters the body through the respiratory system
or an open wound.[15] While most of the depleted uranium is secreted
from the human body after ingestion, significant amounts deposit in
the kidney and bone, and to a lesser extent in other tissues including
the muscle, lung, brain, lymph nodes, and testes.[16] This internal
radiation source has been linked to health problems which include increased
rates of cancer, birth defects, brain lesions, depressed immune systems
and damage to skin, respiratory and digestive tracts.[17] Many civilians
in Iraq and Yugoslavia and US and British veterans have complained of
these health effects several years after the war.[18]
While the military
authorities have denied the contaminating effects of these weapons both
for the environment and the surrounding populations, the US army dossiers
from 1990 have warned about dangers from accidents with DU. The dossier
from 28 September, 1990 warned that no equipment or materials involved
in the accident/incident should be removed until they have been monitored
and decontaminated by radiation protection personal.[19] Just prior
to the Gulf War, the U.S. Army Armament, Munitions, and Chemical Command
released a report which warned that exposures to DU could have radiological
and toxicological effects, to soldiers in the battlefield and
could cause cancer when exposures are internal.[20] Studies by the U.S.
Armed Forces Radiobiology Research Institute have also found that rats
implanted with DU metal were susceptible to cancer, immune system damage,
central nervous system problems, and damage to the male and female reproductive
systems.[21] Another study by the Lovelace Respiratory Research Institute
in New Mexico (funded my the US Army) found that DU fragments cause
cancer when implanted in the muscle of rats.[22] Doug Rokke, ex-director
of the Pentagons depleted uranium project and former professor
of environmental science at Jacksonville University, said that DU weapons
were weapons of mass destruction and its use a war
crime.[23]
The Pentagon, however,
has continuously tried to downplay the effects of DU. It has created
quasi-scientific reports denying that any soldiers and civilians could
be sick from DU ignoring the calls of their own military DU researchers
for further research and investigation.[24] The Pentagon also claimed
that the implication of the studies on rats have remained unclear as
to their effects on humans and that further studies are needed in this
area.[25] The Pentagon also used reports by RAND, Institute of Medicine
(IOM), and the US Department of Veterans Affairs to support their position
on denying the negative effects of DU although they ignored the deficiencies
of the report.[26]
In 1999, The RAND
Corporation released a report stating that it was unlikely that the
health of Gulf War veterans had been affected by DU.[27] However, RAND
based it conclusions on incomplete and misleading exposure
data provided by the Pentagon.[28] The reports independence was also
undermined by the fact that one of its primary authors simultaneously
worked for the Pentagons Gulf War illness investigation.[29] The
IOM conducted an independent US investigation of DU and found that exposure
to very low levels of DU was unlikely to result in the development of
lung cancer or kidney problems.[30] However, the committee admitted
that it lacked accurate exposure information about Gulf War veterans
and civilians to determine whether DU exposure might result in increased
rates of lymphatic and bone cancers, nervous system disease, or immune
system damage.[31] In 1999 the U.S. Department of Veterans Affairs conducted
a study of 51 Gulf War veterans exposed to DU in friendly fire incidents.[32]
The study revealed that only one veteran had Hodgkins lymphoma
and another had a bone tumor.[33] The Pentagon later was forced to acknowledge
that that the fifty-one veterans were only a tiny fraction of the thousands
of veterans that were potentially exposed to DU contamination.[34]
The Pentagon has
also frequently cited the 2001 reports from the World Health Organization
(WHO) and the United Nations Environment Programme (UNEP) Balkans Task
Force in claiming that DU is innocuous.[35] These organizations were
compelled to conduct investigations about the effects of DU use due
to the outcry that had erupted in Europe about the growing number of
unexplained deaths and illnesses among peacekeepers exposed to the hazardous
substance, especially after the war on Yugoslavia.[36] The WHO study
could not identify any illness among local populations directly related
to DU and stated that any radiation was within acceptable levels, but
recommended further health monitoring.[37] UNEPs Balkan Task force
determined that localized contamination at impact sites poses little
immediate health risk to local population, but it expressed concern
about contamination of groundwater and the collection of DU penetrations
by civilians (which was documented in Iraq and Kosovo).[38]
The WHO study, however
was criticized as being unreliable and at odds with current scientific
knowledge.[39] The WHO was accused of not taking a proper epidemiological
study, but only an academic desk study.[40] The WHO was also criticized
for studying DU in narrow terms due to pressure by the International
Atomic Energy Agency.[41] The UNEP study was seen as compromised by
many.[42] This was due to the presence of NATO troops that accompanied
the researchers and prevented them from any contract with DU unexploded
and sub-munitions and even from discovering their existence.[43] The
European Commission reported that up to 95 percent of the DU rounds
shot by American jets did not hit any targets and were likely to be
lying intact on the ground.[44] The UNEP taskforce recommendation that
the appropriate authorities undertake the mark-up and clean up of all
DU contaminated sites has also not been fulfilled by any parties.[45]
The U.S. fears that any such move might force it to concede the dangerous
radioactive effects of DU and might set a precedent for cleanups in
every country where it has been used.[46]
The Pentagon also
ignored or criticized as inadequate other studies that come to different
conclusions about the effects of DU. Roger Coghill, a British biologist,
predicted the use of DU weapons would generate more than 100,000 fatal
cancer cases.[47] Dr. Hari Sharma, of the University of Waterloo in
Ontario and Patricia Horn discovered DU in half of the gulf war vets
they tested several years after the war.[48] A study of cancer and leukemia
in Iraqi soldiers from heavily bombed areas showed extraordinary increases
in lymphoma and brain cancer.[49] The Pentagon dismissed many of these
studies as they have not been peer reviewed despite the surprising similarities
and timing between diseases and deformities in Gulf War veterans, their
families and the Iraqi population that these reports found.[50]
While there isnt
unanimous consent about the extent of radioactive effects of DU, its
use has been so controversial that the U.S and Britain are the only
countries that continue to use it.[51] Most governments, including NATO
governments and U.S. allies such as Germany, Canada, the Czech Republic,
Norway, and the Netherlands have foresworn the use of DU weapons.[52]
Most democratic governments are not willing to accept the health, environmental
and the resulting political problems associated with the use of DU.[53]
The U.N. Commission on Human Rights in 1996 and again in 2002 seemed
to confirm these effects of DU and take a step in the direction of banning
these weapons when it categorized DU as a weapon of indiscriminate
effect and which could violate the international laws of armed
conflict.[54] Unfortunately, unlike European countries, there has been
relatively little discussion or debate about DU in the U.S. as the Pentagon
has continuously refused to acknowledge its dangers despite numerous
reports to the contrary.[55]
III. International
Humanitarian Laws and Depleted Uranium
A. Introduction
The legality of DU would first be governed by the laws of humanitarian
warfare which stipulates the standards for acceptable weapons of warfare.
These standards are laid out in the Hague Conventions of 1899 and 1907,
the Geneva Conventions of 1925 and 1949 and the additional Protocol
I to Geneva added in 1977.[56] Although these principles do apply to
DU use due to its radioactive nature and effects, it would be hard to
justify a total ban solely on these standards due to inconclusive scientific
evidence and the restrictive World Court opinion on nuclear weapons.[57]
B. International
Humanitarian Laws of Warfare
General humanitarianism in war has been accepted by many cultures in
the world, even though they may not be universally adhered to.[58] As
the brutalities of war became apparent at the end of the 18th century,
many nations decided that certain acts of warfare were inhumane
and not necessary for defeating the enemy.[59] What emerged was a body
of international law, termed the humanitarian laws of warfare, which
prohibit certain acts during warfare while not prohibiting war itself.[60]
These principles were accepted by most states, including the U.S. and
U.K.[61]
The Hague Conventions
of 1899 and 1907 were the earliest binding codification of the laws
of warfare to set limits to the means and methods of armed conflict
and define the scope of what may be legitimately used.[62] Article 22
of Hague IV (Laws and Customs of War on Land) states that the
right of belligerents to adopt means of injuring the enemy is not unlimited
and Article 3 directs that a state shall be responsible for all
acts committed by its armed forces. [63] Article 3 has been widely
interpreted to mean that if a state violates the laws of armed conflict,
they should be held responsible to the injured parties.[64] Article
23 of Hague IV states that it is specially forbidden to:
23(a) To employ
poison or poisoned weapons
23(e) To employ
arms, projectiles, or material calculated to cause unnecessary suffering
23(g) To destroy
or seize the enemy's property, unless such destruction or seizure be
imperatively demanded by the necessities of war.[65]
After the use of
gases on a great scale during World War 1 (in violation of the Hague
Convention), the ban on poison gas was addressed more effectively in
the 1925 Geneva Gas Protocol.[66] The Protocol expanded the prohibition
to the use of asphyxiating, poisonous or other gases, and all analogous
substances including bacteriological methods of war.[67] This expansion
was thought necessary due to the persistence of some chemicals and how
they can spread easily across the environment into the food chain.[68]
In keeping with
the scope of articles 23(g) and other core principles of the Hague Conventions,
the customary principles of proportionality, discrimination, humanity
and necessity were developed to apply to armed conflict. The principle
of proportionality prohibits methods of warfare likely to cause injury
to civilians in excess of any concrete and direct military advantage.[69]
The principle of discrimination requires belligerents to discriminate
between military and non-military targets and between combatants and
non-combatants.[70] The humanity principle prohibits wanton attacks
on civilians, as well as acts or threats if the primary purpose is to
terrorize civilians.[71] Finally, principle of military necessity justifies
measures not forbidden by international law which are indispensable
for securing the prompt submission of the enemy with the least possible
loss of economic and human resources.[72]
The Hague Conventions
also deal with the laws of neutrality which apply to means of warfare.
Article 1 of Hague V: Convention Respecting the Rights and Duties of
Neutral Powers in Case of War on Land and Article 1 of Hague XIII: Rights
and Duties of Neutral Powers in Naval war states that:
Hague VII (1) The
territory of neutral Powers is inviolable
Hague XIII (1) Belligerents
are bound to respect the sovereign rights of neutral Powers and to abstain,
in neutral territory or neutral waters, from any act which would, if
knowingly permitted by any Power, constitute a violation of neutrality.[73]
The ICJ in Paragraph
89 of its famous advisory opinion on the use of nuclear weapons said
that these principles of neutrality apply to all international
armed conflict, whatever type of weapons might be used.[74] Hence,
states must respect the laws of neutrality and the sovereign rights
of neutral states when it comes to using weapons in warfare.[75]
There was no direct
reference to the environment in either the Hague or the Geneva Conventions
of 1925 and 1949. The increased awareness of environmental concerns
led to the Additional Protocol I to the 1949 Geneva Conventions.[76]
Protocol I was the first modern convention specifically protecting the
environment in time of war and balanced it with human interests.[77]
The relevant provisions that apply to DU use can be found in articles
35 and 55:
Article 35. Basic
Rules
2. It is prohibited
to employ weapons, projectiles and material and method of warfare of
a nature to cause superfluous injury or unnecessary suffering.
3. It is prohibited
to employ methods of means of warfare which are intended, or may be
expected, to cause widespread, long-term and severe damage to the natural
environment.
Article 55
1. Care shall be
taken in warfare to protect the natural environment against widespread,
long-term and severe damage. This protection includes a prohibition
of the use of methods or means of warfare which are intended or may
be expected to cause such damage to the natural environment and thereby
prejudice the health or survival of the population.[78]
The difference between
Article 35(3) and 55(1) is that the former prohibits causing damage
(with intent) whereas the later imposes a standard of care (human reliance).[79]
The conjunctive use of the terms widespread, long-term, and severe
clearly contemplates a high threshold of damage before the prohibitions
are implicated.[80] Most commentators have interpreted this threshold
to apply to a military act that causes a major interference with human
life or natural resources, which considerably exceeds the battlefield
damage and the effects of which lasts for several decades.[81] Some
see these provisions as directed only at unconventional means of warfare
such as a massive use of herbicides or chemical agents.[82] The later
interpretation however, is subject to debate as such unconventional
means have been addressed separately and specifically in the Biological
and Chemical Weapons Conventions of 1972 and 1993.[83] Once the high
threshold of Article 35(3) and 55(1) have been reached however, they
can override the traditional principles of necessity and proportionality.[84]
In addition to
the environmental provisions, the Additional Protocol formally codifies
the customary international law provisions of indiscriminate attack
and clearly defines it in the following provisions:
Article 51
4. Indiscriminate
attacks are prohibited. Indiscriminate attacks are:
(a) Those which
are not directed at a specific military objective;
(b) Those which
employ a method or means of combat which cannot be directed at a specific
military objective; or
(c) Those which
employ a method or means of combat the effects of which cannot be limited
as required by this Protocol; and consequently, in each such case, are
of a nature to strike military objectives and civilians or civilian
objects without distinction.[85]
Thus, the principle
of indiscriminate attacks provides great protection to civilians as
it calls for the minimization of collateral damage and incidental injury,
especially if they are reasonably foreseen.[86] Most weapons such as
biological and chemical weapons that have been incapable of following
the discrimination principle have been prohibited through conventional
law.[87]
The United States
has signed but not ratified the treaty primarily due to reservations
about targeting dual use facilities and the national liberation
provisions and as they pertain to the law on captives.[88] Despite the
non-ratification, the Regan administration simultaneously announced
its willingness to be bound by those provisions of Geneva Protocol I
that enunciate customary international law.[89] The U.S. acknowledged
that most of Protocol I is customary law and thus binding on its armed
forces.[90] It is unclear however, whether the U.S. views these particular
environmental provisions as part of customary international law as it
has called them excessively broad and expressed reservations about them.[91]
Another principle
found in the Geneva Convention Additional Protocol of 1977 and which
is also part of customary international law is the Martens Clause.[92]
The Martens Clause confirms that the laws of war apply to weapons and
methods of warfare not specifically mentioned in different conventions
and those weapons could be prohibited despite the lack of a convention
that bans them.[93] The burden of proof was on the state using the new
weapon to justify its use under the existing norms of international
humanitarian laws.[94] This principle was originally set forth in the
preamble of Hague IV of 1907 and shows that even the drafters of the
convention then understood that technological advancement could lead
to new weapons which could be more destructive and inhumane than weapons
that were already banned like expanding bullets or poison.[95] The ICJ
used this principle in finding nuclear weapons illegal, despite the
absence of a convention prohibiting its use.[96]
C. DU and International
Humanitarian Law
The first principle to be analyzed is whether DU is a weapon which causes
unnecessary or aggravated devastation or suffering in violation of Hague
IV 23(e) and Geneva additional Protocol I 35(2). As mentioned before,
DU particles can cause long-lasting health problems when ingested by
military personal and civilians (possibly for the rest of their lives).[97]
It can remain in the liver, kidney, bones or other tissues, eradicating
those tissues for years.[98] Even the Department of Defence (DOD) admits
that the shrapnel and gasses released from a DU weapon are radioactive.[99]
This is even more concerning as most DU use tends to be around urban
areas, where people live, work, draw water and grow food and are thus
more likely to suffer its radioactive effects.[100] These radioactive
effects could also have an impact on the environment and be covered
by Hague IV 23(e) as any human suffering caused by environmental damage
would be within the scope of the principle.[101]
Both the U.S. and
NATO countries, however, have denied the health and environmental effects
of DU and rely on certain international reports to complement their
views and reject others that contradict it.[102] It could be argued
that the U.S. and NATOs refusal to even acknowledge some dangers
of DU use is extraordinary in light of the proliferation of reports
warning about possible harms in the last ten years as well as very lethal
nature of the substance.[103] The U.S. and NATO have also relied on
inconclusive reports to come to their bold conclusion denying any serious
health effects of DU use and have often misled the public, the press
and Congress about the matter.[104] Most of their initial studies of
the armed forces dealt with the effects of DU on their own personal
and not their targets.[105] Despite the flaws in the evidence put forth
by the U.S. and NATO, it is unlikely that the effects of DU use can
be established for certain.[106] In order to ban the use of DU or to
compel nations to stop using it due to unnecessary or aggravated devastation
or suffering, more definitive scientific studies are necessary.[107]
These studies, however, would need to be conclusive and study the effects
on combatants and non-combatants alike.[108]
Another shortcoming
of the principle of unnecessary or aggravated devastation or suffering
is that DU users may insist that there is no alternative to its use
in most situations in order to achieve the military objective.[109]
They would argue that there is no useable metal as hard as uranium and
therefore any of the suffering that accompanies DU use is necessary.[110]
The only alterative is the use of tungsten which is not as effective
and needs to be imported as opposed to DU which is a waste product from
the nuclear industry (and costs nothing.)[111]
The prohibition
against indiscriminate harm as a basis of customary international law
and as stipulated in Geneva Additional Protocol I 51(4) is more applicable
to DU as it cannot be derogated by military necessity.[112] DU shells
spread over vast areas and can remain lethal for thousands of years
or longer. [113] The U.S. Armys Environmental Policy Institute
stated in 1995 that radioactivity only begins to diminish after 4,500
million years.[114]
Although the impact
of a DU weapons can be contained within the targeted area, its spread
after impact cannot.[115] Upon contact, the uranium metal partially
burns producing uranium oxide which can be spread by the wind to great
distances.[116] When released in the air, it can be internalized by
breathing smoke containing DU particles, ingestion of food or water
contaminated by DU, inhalation or ingestion of resuspended particles
or contamination of wounds by DU dust.[117] Scientists in Greece reported
that radiation levels there increased by twenty-five percent when winds
would blow in from Kosovo and similar concerns have been voiced about
Kuwait.[118] In addition, there are numerous DU projectiles in Iraq
that have been left on the ground after the war and since been covered
with sand.[119] As rain falls in these desert regions, the toxic substances
permeate the ground water and enter the food chain.[120] Most doctors
and scientists agree that even mild radiation is dangerous and can increase
the risk of illnesses like cancer.[121] These factors show that protected
civilians would be threatened even if they were a long distance from
the target.[122] Such incidents have occurred as cancers have been found
among Iraqi refugees in Iran who were near areas that came under allied
fire close to the border of Kuwait.[123]
DUs use would
also affect the offspring of military personal and civilians that might
have come in contact with and ingested it.[124] It is estimated that
sixty-seven percent of children born to U.S. Gulf War veterans had severe
illness or birth defects.[125] Also, studies by Iraqi doctors have found
that DU is responsible for an increase in stillbirth and birth defects
such as babies born with no eyes, brains, limbs, genitalia, internal
organs on the outside and grotesquely deformed little heads and bodies.[126]
Despite the fact that these reports are not fully conclusive, any indiscriminate
harm that DU would cause these offspring would be contrary to humanitarian
principles as they are non-combatants.[127]
The problem that
arises with this argument is that all states accept the fact that a
certain amount of collateral damage will occur to civilians when military
facilities and personal are targeted.[128] To ban DU weapons with the
indiscriminate harm argument it would need to be proven that disproportionate
damage to civilians actually occurred in relation to the military purpose.[129]
However, it is the duty of the party using DU weapons to minimize collateral
damage and incidental injury as much as possible even if that requires
those conducting military operations to forgo causing that which could
be reasonably avoided.[130] If the consequences of DU radioactive particles
to non-combatants were more apparent and internationally recognized,
the decision to use these weapons would be considered excessive and
hence illegal.[131]
The laws of neutrality
could also be violated by the fact that the effects of DU cannot be
contained in all instances and it could spread through wind and water
systems and thus be unable respect the territorial integrity of a neutral
state.[132] DU users would however claim that the spill over effect
to neutral states is unintentional and therefore not prohibited.[133]
The provisions of the Hague conventions dealing with neutrality do not
address unintentional violations of neutrality but neither do they specifically
state that violations of neutrality must be intentional.[134]
Christopher Weeramanty,
a judge on the ICJ for the nuclear weapons case said that if the consequences
of an action are known beforehand, one cannot claim nor avoid responsibility
for them.[135] In his dissenting opinion he stated that:
It is not to point
that such results are not directly intended, but are by-products
or collateral damage. The author of the act causing these
consequences cannot in any coherent legal system avoid legal responsibility
for causing them any more than a man careering in a motor vehicle at
a hundred and fifty kilometers per hour through a crowded market street
can avoid responsibility for the resulting deaths on the grounds that
he did not intend to kill the particular persons who died.[136]
The ICJ, however,
did not conclude that transborder damage from nuclear weapons would
be sufficient in every circumstance to ban its use.[137] So even though
DU weapons may be deemed illegal due to transborder damage in some cases,
it is unclear if this would apply in every situation.[138] Therefore,
it would be difficult to call for a general prohibition of DU weapons
on this principle.[139]
It might appear
that the prohibition against the use of poison or poisoned weapons in
war would apply to DU due to the potential of radioactive poisoning
which can be more devastating to human health that the other prohibited
poisons.[140] Some theorists expanded on this interpretation when they
stated that Iraqs release of oil, and burning of oil to produce
fumes fell under this definition as did the use of chemical defoliants
on forests and agricultural lands by the U.S. in Vietnam and Laos.[141]
The ICJ, however interpreted poisoned weapons to only include weapons
whose prime, or even exclusive, effect is to poison or asphyxiate.[142]
The prime purpose of DU is not to poison but to penetrate hard armor.[143]
Although the court
had a restrictive interpretation of the use of poison and poisoned weapons,
their interpretations were opposed in the dissenting opinions of judges
Weeramanty and Koroma.[144] They reinforced the concept that the poisonous
radiation effects of nuclear weapons in almost all cases would be more
harmful than those poisons that are prohibited.[145] Justice Weeramanty
noted that radiation poisoning is more insidious than poison gas as
its effects include the transmission to genetic disorders for
generations. [146] The Justice also noted that even though radiation
is a by-product of nuclear weapons, its poisonous effects couldnt
be unintended as it is well known that radiation is a major consequence
of the bomb.[147] It is possible that these interpretations by Kormoa
and Weeramantry will eventually become the norm for poisoned weapons
and apply to DU as the threats posed by it parallel the larger threats
of gas and nuclear weapons.[148]
Finally, it could
be argued that DUs use does cause widespread, long-term and severe
damage to the environment despite the dubiousness of the this principle
as it applies to the U.S.[149] Although international humanitarian law
has yet to limit the use of a weapon because of its environmental consequences,
it provides de facto protection to the environment through setting standards
for prohibiting certain weapons that harm it.[150] As discussed before,
the effects of DU lasts more than several decades and spreads over wide
areas.[151] While there is no conclusive definition as to the exact
meaning of long-term or widespread, it is hard to deny that
the radiological effects of DU would not transcend battlefield damage.[152]
The World Court has itself stated that the effects of radiation for
the environment can be catastrophic as it would effect agriculture,
natural resources, and demography over a wide area.[153] The Court also
stated that radiation had the potential to damage the future environment,
food and marine ecosystem, and to cause genetic defects and illness
in future generations.[154]
The ICJ, however,
also determined that environmental damage must be considered with relation
to military necessity and proportionality.[155] The court stated that
when looking at these principles holistically, they could condemn every
use of nuclear weapons on environmental protection outright.[156] It
would be difficult to claim that the use of DU would have a greater
environmental effect than that of nuclear weapons.[157] The only possible
basis for counterargument would be that DU weapons are used widely,
whereas nuclear weapons are not. It is estimated that U.S. armed forces
used more than 14,000 rounds in Iraq during the first Gulf war and 31,000
rounds in Yugoslavia.[158] However, it would still be hard to measure
how much of the environmental damage resulted from DU use as opposed
to the environmental policies of the governments of the country under
attack.[159]
IV. International
Environmental Law Principles and Depleted Uranium
A. Introduction
While the legality
of DU use according to the principles of international humanitarian
law are dubious, a stronger case can be made for it violating the emerging
principles of international environmental law such as the precautionary
principle and intergenerational equity.[160] These principles apply
to DU use as they lack a requirement of conclusive scientific certainty
and expose the U.S. and NATO for failing to take any measures to prevent
or remedy the harm caused to other nations or future generations by
the use of this toxic weapon.[161] Unfortunately, the status of these
principles as part of customary international law have not been established
for them to be binding.[162]
B. The Precautionary
Principle and Intergenerational Equity
The precautionary
principle provides that when there is reason to believe that a particular
practice would generate trans border environmental damage, the practicing
party has to take preventive measures to prove its safety even if there
is a lack of conclusive scientific evidence about its effects.[163]
Such preventive measures could include planning, alternatives assessment,
and anticipatory action to avoid environmental damage.[164] The principle
emerged from the recognition that scientific certainty comes too late
to design effective legal and policy responses for preventing environmental
threats.[165] The principle shifts the burden of scientific proof necessary
for triggering policy responses from those whose support prohibiting
a harmful activity to those who want to continue the activity.[166]
The question of
when the obligation arises for the offending state is answered in the
Trail Smelter arbitration concerning Canadian transboundary pollution
that caused damaged to the U.S. and the Crofu Channel case involving
British Navy Ships damaged due to mines in Albanias territorial
sea.[167] The Trail Smelter cases suggests that the obligation arises
on the state for transboundary damage if there is an actual and serious
harm that is likely to recur as a result of their actions and the injury
is established by clear and convincing evidence.[168] The Corfu Channel
cases stated that the responsibility is triggered when there is a known
risk to other states.[169]
The precautionary
principle was inspired by its use in Swedish and German environmental
law and policy and first employed internationally in the North Sea Conference
in 1984.[170] It was later affirmed by the EC governments in the 1990
Bergen Ministerial Declaration on Sustainable Development and secured
global endorsement in Principle 15 of the 1992 Rio Declaration on Environment
and Development.[171]
The extent that
this principle has been applied internationally to form an opinio juris
of customary international law is unclear.[172] It has been accepted
as a principle of international law by the EU, Canada, the Supreme Courts
of India and Pakistan, and many other nations, and has been used as
a policy in numerous legally binding treaties.[173] But the U.S. has
denied that it is part of customary international law and the WTO appellate
body in the Beef Hormones case found its legal status uncertain.[174]
There also have been uncertainties pertaining to its meaning, application
and implications which work against it being recognized as a concrete
principle of customary international law.[175] Despite these uncertainties,
its use by national and international courts, by international organizations,
and in treaties shows that this principle is a legally important concept.
[176]
The principle of
Intergenerational equity states that it is the responsibility of each
generation to use and develop its natural and cultural heritage in a
manner that it can be passed on to future generations in no worse a
condition than it was received.[177] Central to this idea is that subsequent
generations should not be threatened by current practice that may disrupt
the use or quality of resources, including that of the natural environment.[178]
This rule is referred to in Principle 3 or the 1992 Rio Declaration
and Article 3(1) of the 1992 Convention on Climate Change.[179]
Although these international
declarations indicate the importance of this policy, it is difficult
to translate this concept into a formal body of law or into rights for
indeterminate generations.[180] While the Philippines Supreme
Court allowed the plaintiffs standing to sue on behalf of themselves
and future generations in a case challenging the grant of timer licenses,
the Bangladesh Supreme Court did not follow this precedent.[181] The
theory has also been criticized for resting on some questionable assumptions
pertaining to the nature of economic equity, despite being well defined.[182]
C. DU and the
Principles of International Environmental Law
The use of DU would
violate the precautionary principle. U.S. and NATO countries have failed
to prove the safety of DU before using it in the battlefield, knowing
that it would cause transboundry damage due to its radioactive nature
and the spreading of uranium oxide over great distances.[183] They have
not taken any preventive measures to avoid the radioactive effects of
DU, have refused to cooperate with many environmental impact studies,
and have refused to clean up contaminated sites.[184] They have falsely
relied on politicized and inconclusive reports on the supposed safety
of DU and failed to even follow their own conclusions pertaining to
further investigations or clean up.[185] In addition, the U.S and NATO
have completely dismissed all reports which have warned of the dangers
of DUs use, despite warning their own military and humanitarian
personal to stay away from areas that were contaminated and putting
warning signs outside the sites themselves.[186] These factors can only
lead to the conclusion that the U.S. acted more callously than the defendants
in the Trail Smelter and Crofu Channel cases.[187]
But in order for
this principle to apply effectively, some concrete transborder environmental
damage has to be claimed by another nation state which they would be
able to prove.[188] Sporadic claims or speculation would not be sufficient.
While formal concerns have been raised by Bulgarian and Romanian officials
about toxic chemical effects of bombed chemical facilities in Yugoslavia,
no such effects have been claimed about DU yet.[189]
The use of DU would
also violate the principle of intergenerational equity in light of the
fact that radiation released by it would effect subsequent generations
both in terms of genetic damage and offspring.[190] Also, uranium would
remain radioactive over an extremely long period of time causing widespread
environmental damage and endangering the resources of future generations.[191]
The U.S. and NATO countries have refused to even consider these harms
before deciding to use DU ammunitions and ignored studies documenting
birth defects to offspring of their own military personal exposed to
this toxic substance.[192]
The only problem
with the precautionary principle and intergenerational equity is their
dubious legal status as they are new emerging concepts in international
environmental law.[193] Despite the fact that they may not be binding,
they do provide an important framework to analyze the recklessness of
parties who choose to use destructive weapons with catastrophic effects.
These principles are already considered important legal concepts and
it is likely that they will be more binding in the future.[194]
V. Conclusion
While the current
situation surrounding DU use might not be sufficient to have the illegality
affirmed by the UN or the ICJ, efforts should continue to strengthen
such law until these weapons are universally banned like expanding bullets
and poisonous gases.[195] This is because DU remains a very lethal substance
and nations are unlikely to apply unilateral prescriptions against its
use due to their own self-interest.[196] The latter can be seen in the
bizarre and irresponsible actions of the U.S. which has done everything
in its power to avoid drawing negative attention to DU and to avoid
liability for its consequences.[197]
Public pressure
should also continue to force the U.S. and NATO countries to clean up
the contaminated sites that they are responsible for.[198] In addition,
legal action should be brought in specific cases for negligence in order
to get some redress from the negative health effects of DU.[199] These
local judicial decisions can be utilized as a subsidiary means to determine
the rules of international law according to article 38(1)(d) of the
Statute of the ICJ.[200] To help better define the legality of DU, pressure
should also mount to get more conclusive and objective studies about
its effects on combatants and non-combatants and to stop parties like
the U.S. from compromising studies put forth by UN and the WHO.[201]
Such pressure has been successful in the past with the anti-nuclear
weapons campaign leading to the World Court opinion against the use
of nuclear weapons.[202]
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
[1] See Dan Fahey,
The Final Word on Depleted Uranium, 25 Fletcher F. World Aff. 189 (2001).
[2] See Section
II.
[3] Alyn Ware, Depleted
Uranium Weapons and International Law in Metal of Dishonor: How the
Pentagon Radiates Soldiers and Civilians with DU weapons 201 (John Catalinotto
and Sara Flounders eds., New York: International Action Center, 1999).
[4] See Section
III.
[5] See Section
IV.
[6] Christine Abdelkrim-Delanne,
Not such conventional weapons, Le Monde Diplomatique, June
1999.
[7] Id.
[8] Robert James
Parsons, Americas big dirty secret, Le Monde Diplomatique,
March 2002.
[9] See supra note
6.
[10] Jacques Brillot,
The chemical effects of DU, Le Monde Diplomatique, February
2001.
[11] Id.
[12] See supra note
6.
[13] Id.
[14] See supra note
8.
[15] See supra note
1 at 191.
[16] Id.
[17] Bukowski, G.D.
Lopez, and F. McGehee, Uranium Battlefields Home and Abroad,
Citizen Alert, March 1993, p. 43-54; Olivera Medecina, Protocol I and
Operation Allied Force: Did NATO abide by Principles of Proportionality?,
23 Loy. L.A. Intl & Comp. L. Rev. 329, 400 (2001).
[18] Id.
[19] Guidelines
for safe response to handling, storage and transportation accidents
involving army tank munitions or armor which contain depleted uranium,
US Department of the Army, Technical Bulletin, TB 9-1300-278.
[20] M.E. Danesi,
Kinetic Energy Penetrator Long Term Strategy Study (Picatinny Arsenal,
NJ: U.S. Army Armament, Munitions, and Chemical Command: 1990), Appendix
D: Vol 1, 4-5; Vol. 1, 2-2; Vol. 2, 3-4.
[21] Supra note
1 at 191.
[22] Id.
[23] Neil Mackay,
US forces use of Depleted Uranium weapons is illegal, Sunday
Herald, 30 March 2003.
[24] Supra note
1 at 196.
[25] Id. at 191.
[26] Id. at 196.
[27] Id.
[28] Id.
[29] Id.
[30] Id.
[31] Id.
[32] Id. at 197.
[33] Id.
[34] Id.
[35] Robert James
Parsons, Americas big dirty secret, Le Monde Diplomatique,
March 2002.
[36] Robert James
Parsons, Deafening silence on depleted uranium, Le Monde
Diplomatique, February 2001.
[37] Id.
[38] Supra note
1 at 189, 198.
[39] Supra note
36.
[40] See supra note
35.
[41] Id.
[42] Id.
[43] Id.
[44] European Commission,
Directorate General, Environment (EURATOM), Opinion of the Group
of Experts Established According to Article 31 of the Euratom Treaty,
Depleted Uranium, (Luxembourg, March 6, 2001), 15.
[45] See supra note
1 at 198.
[46] Id.
[47] Jeremy T Burton,
Depleted Morality: Yugoslavia v. Ten NATO members and Depleted Uranium,
19 Wis. Intl L.J. 17, 31 (2000).
[48] Id.
[49] See Medecina
supra note 17 at 402.
[50] Id.
[51] Id. at 200.
[52] Id.
[53] Id.
[54] See supra note
23; Philippa Winkler, UN sub-commission on human rights votes ban on
DU, in Metal of Dishonor: How the Pentagon Radiates Soldiers and Civilians
with DU weapons 191-93 (John Catalinotto and Sara Flounders eds., New
York: International Action Center, 1999).
[55] See supra note
47 at 32.
[56] Nicholas G.
Alexander, Air strikes and Environmental Damage: Can the United States
Be Held Liable for Operation Allied Force? 11 Colo. J. Intl. Envtl.
L. & Poly 471, 475-81.
[57] Supra note
3 at 198-201.
[58] Id. at 196.
[59] Id. at 195.
[60] Id.
[61] Id. at 197.
[62] Supra note
56 at 475-76.
[63] Convention
Respecting the Laws and Customs of War on Land, Oct 18, 1907, art. 3
and 22 {Hereinafter Hague IV} available at http://www.yale.edu/lawweb/avalon/lawofwar/hague04.htm
(last visited May 5 2004.)
[64] See supra note
56 at 476.
[65] Hague IV, supra
note 64, art. 23 available at http://www.yale.edu/lawweb/avalon/lawofwar/hague04.htm
(last visited May 5, 2004)
[66] Michael N.
Schmitt, Humanitarian Law and the Environment, 28 Denv. J. Intl
L. & Poly 265, 285 (2000).
[67] Id.
[68] Id.
[69] Richard A.
Falk, Environmental Warfare and Ecocide, in 4 THE VIETNAM WAR AND INTERNATIONAL
LAW 287, 289 (Richard A. Falk ed., 1976).
[70] Id.
[71] Id. The humanity
principle can be violated with respect to the environment in many ways,
such as poisoning water supplies, dispersing chemical or biological
agencies to infect a human population or contaminate its crops or livestock,
or destroying a populations food source directly, or by a blockade.
[72] Id.
[73] Convention
Respecting the Rights and Duties of Neutral Powers in Case of War on
Land, October 18, 1907, Art. 1, {hereinafter Hague V Convention} available
at http://www.yale.edu/lawweb/avalon/lawofwar/hague04.htm; Convention
respecting the Rights and Duties of Neutral Powers in Naval Wars, October
18 1907, Art. 1 {hereinafter Hague XIII} available at http://www.yale.edu/lawweb/avalon/lawofwar/hague13.htm
(last visited 5/5/03.)
[74] Advisory Opinion
on the Legality of the Threat or use of Nuclear Weapons, 1996 I.C.J.
226, paragraph 89.
[75] Francis Boyle,
The Criminality of Nuclear Deterrence, 190 (Atlanta, GA: Clarity Press,
2002).
[76] Aaron Schwabach,
Environmental Damage Resulting from the NATO Military Action Against
Yugoslavia, 25 Colum. J. Envtl. L. 117, 126 (2000).
[77] John Alan Cohen,
Modes of Warfare and Evolving Standards of Environmental Protection
Under the International Law of War, 15 Fla. J. Intl L. 481, 501
(2003).
[78] Protocol Additional
to the Geneva Conventions of 12 August 1949, and relating to the protection
of victims of International Armed Conflicts, 8 June , 1977, Art. 35
and 55 {hereinafter Protocol 1} available at http://www.unhchr.ch/html/menu3/b/93.htm
(last visited May 5, 2004.)
[79] Supra note
66 at 276-77.
[80] Supra note
77 at 502.
[81] Id. at 502-03.
[82] Id. at 504-05.
[83] Id. at 505.
[84] Id.
[85] Protocol I
supra note 78, Art. 51.
[86] See supra note
66 at 311-12. In addition to distinguishing between civilian and military
objectives.
[87] Id. at 311.
[88] Supra note
76 at 126.
[89] Supra note
75 at 179.
[90] Michael Schmitt,
Green War: An Assessment of the Environmental Law of International Armed
Conflict, 22 YJIL 1, 69 (1997).
[91] Id.; See supra
note 66 at 278.
[92] See supra note
3 at 197-98.
[93] Id. at 198.
[94] See supra note
75 at 103.
[95] See supra note
3 at 198.
[96] Id.
[97] See supra notes
15-23 and accompanying text.
[98] See supra note
17 at 400.
[99] See supra note
47 at 35.
[100] Environment
in Iraq: UNEP Progress report, Geneva, Nairobi, Kenya: United Nations
Environmental Programme, pg. 21 (2003).
[101] See supra
note 66 at 296.
[102] See supra
notes 26, 47-50.
[103] See supra
note 17 at 403.
[104] See supra
notes 47-50 and note 1 at 199.
[105] See supra
note 47 at 39.
[106] Id.
[107] Id.
[108] Id.
[109] See supra
note 3 at 198.
[110] Id.
[111] See supra
note 6.
[112] See Medecina
supra note 17 at 401.
[113] See supra
note 3 at 198.
[114] See Medecina
supra note 17 at 404.
[115] See supra
note 3 at 198.
[116] See supra
note 12 and 13 and accompanying text.
[117] See Medecina
supra note 17 at 400.
[118] See supra
note 47 at 31; Scott Peterson, DUs global spread spurs debate
over effect on humans, Christian Science Monitor, April 29, 1999.
[119] Dr. Siegwart-Horst
Guenther, How DU Shell Residues Poison Iraq, Kuwait and Saudi Arabia,
in Metal of Dishonor: How the Pentagon Radiates Soldiers and Civilians
with DU weapons 168 (John Catalinotto and Sara Flounders eds., New York:
International Action Center, 1999).
[120] Id.
[121] Eric Hoskins,
Depleted Uranium Shells make the Desert Glow in Metal of Dishonor: How
the Pentagon Radiates Soldiers and Civilians with DU weapons 165 (John
Catalinotto and Sara Flounders eds., New York: International Action
Center, 1999).
[122] See supra
note 3 at 199.
[123] Robert Fisk,
The Truth About Depleted Uranium, The Independent, 8 January
2001.
[124] Id.
[125] See Medecina
supra note 17 at 402.
[126] Id. at 403.
[127] See supra
note 3 at 199.
[128] Id.
[129] Id.
[130] See supra
note 67 at 311.
[131] See Medecina
supra note 17 at 402.
[132] Supra note
3 at 199.
[133] Id.
[134] Id.
[135] Advisory Opinion
on the Legality of the Threat or use of Nuclear Weapons, 1996 I.C.J.
226, Dissenting Opinion of Judge Weeramanty.
[136] Id.
[137] Supra note
3 at 200.
[138] Id.
[139] Id.
[140] Id.
[141] See supra
note 76 at 124.
[142]Advisory Opinion
on the Legality of the Threat or use of Nuclear Weapons, 1996 I.C.J.
226, paragraph 55.
[143] See supra
note 3 at 200.
[144] Supra note
135; Advisory Opinion on the Legality of the Threat or use of Nuclear
Weapons, 1996 I.C.J. 226, Dissenting opinion of Judge Koroma.
[145] Supra note
135.
[146] Id.
[147] Id.
[148].See supra
note 47 at 37.
[149] See supra
note 3 at 200.
[150] See supra
note 67 at 285.
[151] See notes
113-123 and accompanying text.
[152] See supra
note 78 at 502.
[153] Advisory Opinion
paragraph 35.
[154] Id.
[155] See supra
note 75 at paragraph 32.
[156] Id. at paragraph
33.
[157] See supra
note 3 at 200.
[158] See supra
note 1 at 194 and note 17 at 402.
[159] Final Report
to the Prosecutor by the Committee Established to Review the NATO Bombing
Campaign Against the Federal Republic of Yugoslavia (2000).
[160] See section
III C.
[161] Id.
[162] See supra
notes 173-76, 180-82 and accompanying text.
[163] Rachel Morello-Frosch,
Manuel Pastor Jr., and James Sadd, Epidemiology and Science: Integrating
Environmental Justice and the Precautionary Principle in Research and
Policy Making, 584 Annals 47, 50 (2002).
[164] Id.
[165] Patricia Birnie
and Alan Boyle, International Law & The Environment 117 (New York:
Oxford University Press, 2002).
[166] Id.
[167] Justin Mellor,
The Negative effects of Chernobyl on International Environmental Law,
17 Wis. Intl L.J. 65, 75 (1999).
[168] Id.; Elizabeth
A. Ellis, Bordering on Disaster: A new attempt to control the Trasnsboundary
effects of Maquiladora Pollution, 30 Val. U.L. Rev, 621, 635-36 (1996);
Martin G. Gelfand, Practical Application of International Environmental
Law: Does it work at all?. 29 Case W. Res. J. Intl L, 73, 77-78
(1997).
[169] Id. Albania
was found negligent of this responsibility and had to pay Britain reparations
for the damages to its ships.
[170] See supra
note 165 at 118.
[171] Id.
[172] Id.
[173] Id.
[174] Id. at 118-19.
[175] Id.
[176] Id. at 120.
[177] Id. at 89.
[178] Id.
[179] Id. at 90.
[180] Id.
[181] Id. at 91.
[182] Id.
[183] See notes
113-21.
[184] See supra
notes 45-47 and accompanying text; NATO hindered Kosovo inquiry,
Financial Times, October 15, 1999.
[185] See supra
notes 28-47 and accompanying text.
[186] See supra
note 1 at 194 and notes 47-50 with accompanying text; Robert Fisk, NATO
Obstructs and Inquiry Into Depleted Uranium, The Independent,
October 16, 1999.
[187] See supra
notes 167-69 and accompanying text.
[188] See supra
note 168 and accompanying text.
[189] Ida L. Bostian,
The Environmental Consequences of the Kosovo Conflict and the NATO Bombing
of Serbia, 1999 Colo. J. Intl Envtl L & Poly 230, 234-35
(2000).
[190] See supra
note 3 at 201 and notes 124-27.
[191] Id.; See supra
notes 153-54 and accompanying text.
[192] See supra
note 1 at 193-94.
[193] See supra
notes 173-176, 180-82 and accompanying text.
[194] See supra
note 165 at 180.
[195] See supra
note 3 at 197, 201.
[196] Id. at 202.
[197] See supra
note 1 at 194.
[198] See supra
note 1 at 199-200.
[199] See supra
note 3 at 201;
[200] Statue of
the International Court of Justice, art. 38(1)(d), reprinted in Basic
Documents of the United Nations 228 (L. Sohn Ed. 1968).
[201] See supra
note 47 at 39-40.
[202] See supra
note 3 at 201.